等级:中尉 文章:378 金钱:332 门派:欠债者权益保护协会 注册:2005-10-20
| For the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics January 5, 2005 word count: 5398 “Socialism” by John E. Roemer1 In the Marxian theory of historical materialism, the ruling class in each mode of production has its special method for extracting the economic surplus from the direct producers; that method follows from the characteristic property relations under the mode. Under the slave mode, the surplus produced by slaves is forcibly appropriated by the slave owner; under feudalism, the lord extracts surplus serf labor through the corvée and various forms of taxation. Capitalism, Marx argued, was the first mode in which surplus extraction was not obviously coercive: no capitalist owns his workers or forcibly takes their product. Indeed, under capitalism, workers and capitalists form contracts in which labor power is exchanged for a wage. The capitalist keeps the product of the worker’s labor. Indeed, Marx wished to explain capitalist surplus extraction as a process that would emerge under competitive contracting, in which workers and capitalists bargain and, in the end, competitive markets set the terms of labor exchange. (As Makowski and Ostroy have written, prices are what appear after the dust of the competitive brawl has cleared. It is incorrect to think of prices as directing trade; rather, bargaining among many pairs of individuals reaches an equilibrium summarized by a price.) Why is it that capitalists end up getting the better part of the deal – that is, they end up with the surplus, and the worker ends up with his wage, which in the Marxian view was only enough for him to subsist upon? The answer lies not in the fact that the capitalist is more clever or has the police on his side: it is that capital is scarce relative to the available supply of labor, and workers must bid for the right to use that scarce capital, which provides them with a wage. Were labor scarce, then capital would have to bid for labor, and profits would be bid down to a minimal level, at which capitalists were indifferent between continuing to own capital and becoming workers. Why capitalism seems to have been characterized, throughout its history, as a situation of capital scarcity is not fully understood. Marx argued that capitalists as a class, perhaps represented by 1 Yale University. 2 the state, undertook strategies to guarantee a ‘reserve army of the unemployed,’ in order to maintain the imbalance. Indeed, the proletarianization of the agricultural periphery is an important process by which labor abundance has been maintained until the present (see Rosa Luxemburg). Keynes and Schumpeter envisaged a time when capital would cease to be scarce, bringing about the euthanasia of the capitalist class. Thus, the fundamental source of the accumulation of wealth in the hands of a small class, through profits created in production, is that abundant workers must bid for the ‘privilege’ of using their labor power on privately owned productive assets that increase its productivity immensely. This provides them with a wage greater than they could have earned in the non-capitalist sector (back on the family farm, so to speak, or selling apples from a street cart), and also produces an additional amount that, according to the labor-capitalist bargain, belongs to the capitalist. Capitalists consume a part of this surplus product, and invest the rest in other profit-making activities. Some writers have argued that capitalism is a system that extracts the surplus from workers coercively; they point to the struggles between workers and bosses at the point of production. It is, I believe, important to point out that capitalist accumulation could transpire, in principle, if capitalists were competitive, and if coercion at the point of production of the worker by the capitalist and his agents did not occur. That coercion, upon which many have focused as a central evil of capitalism, only exists because labor contracts are incomplete and not costlessly enforceable. Imagine that the worker and capitalist could contract about every eventuality that might occur during production. If, in addition, the contract were costlessly enforceable (imagine an omnipotent arbitrator who is at hand to deal with any disagreement), then there would be no petty coercion at the point of production: capitalists would not try to speed up assembly lines, force workers to work overtime, cheat them of their wages, discipline them in demeaning ways, and so on. I believe that Marx thought that the essence of capitalism was the accumulation of capital even under such conditions. That actual capitalism is not perfectly competitive, that contracts are incomplete, and that capitalists and workers will haggle over who is to do what when a situation not described in the contract comes up, is something which makes capitalism more unpleasant than the ideal type would be, but is not of its essence. 3 Marx believed that the property relations of each mode of production would last only so long as they succeeded in inducing production in an efficient way. “The water mill gives us the feudal lord, the steam engine, the industrial capitalist.” He believed that eventually productive forces would develop to such an extent that the capitalist mode of extracting economic surplus would no longer be effective. Indeed, the next stage in economic history, Marx conjectured, would be socialism, a period in which the means of production were collectively owned and the economic surplus thereby became the property of the workers. We must define exploitation in the Marxian sense. Marx said that workers were exploited because the labor required to produce the goods they could purchase with their wages – including the labor needed to reproduce the capital stock used up in that production – was smaller in quantity that the labor expended by workers for which they received those wage goods. The ‘surplus’ labor, the difference between these two quantities, became embodied in goods which, according to the contract, are owned by capitalists, and which they sell for profit. Why does the worker put up with this situation? Because he has no access to the means of production; the surplus labor he supplies is, so to speak, the rent he pays the capitalist for access to those means. Exploitation is defined as the fact that workers labor for more hours than are ‘embodied’ in the goods they receive as the real wage. Note that, although Marx insisted the wage was one of subsistence, this is entirely unnecessary for the argument. All that must be the case, for exploitation to exist, is that the hours of labor embodied in goods which wages purchase are less than the hours worked by workers. Marx viewed socialism as the system that would end capitalist exploitation, in this sense. There are, however, at least prime facie, several ways of ending exploitation short of collectivizing ownership in the means of production, and hence in collectivizing the product they produce above what workers receive as wages. One is syndicalism, in which groups of workers own their factories collectively; another is people’s capitalism, a system in which firms are privately owned by citizens, each of whom owns a small share of all firms. Syndicalism would quickly generate a system with highly unequal ownership of productive assets, so some groups of workers would ‘exploit’ others through trade, not to speak of hiring contract laborers. Designing a people’s capitalism 4 in which Marxian exploitation were eliminated is possible in the abstract, but it would be difficult to implement in actuality. One should note that the distribution of shares in firms to citizens that would abolish exploitation could not be an equal one. Consider the situation of a person who does not work out of choice (a ‘surfer’), but collects dividends: he would be exploiting others, in the Marxian sense, because the amount of labor embodied in the goods he can purchase with his income is greater than the labor he expends. Indeed, for exploitation to be abolished ( in the sense that the labor accounts balance) those who choose not to work should receive zero shares of the capital stock. It is in fact possible to design a system of share ownership so that, when individuals choose their labor supply to maximize their preferences over labor and income, the income they receive from wages and their dividends is precisely enough to purchase goods embodying exactly the labor they expended, and in addition, the allocation of labor and goods is Pareto efficient. This arrangement, called the proportional solution by Joaquim Silvestre, solves an interesting intellectual problem, but it has little importance as a way of solving the problem of capitalist exploitation, because of the difficulty of actually computing the shares of firms citizens should receive, when information about preferences is asymmetric. (The proportional solution, however, may be used by a small community [for example of fisherman] who collectively own a resource [such as a lake] and wish to exploit it efficiently, avoiding congestion and overuse.) Moreover, as we shall see below, it is not necessarily ethically desirable if workers are significantly heterogeneous in skill. Socialism, then, became identified with collectivization of the means of production. Workers would produce more goods than they consumed (nobody claims that investment should be zero under socialism), but the existence of a surplus product would not constitute exploitation because it would be owned by all. This presumably meant that the state, which represented the working class, would decide upon its use. Whether this would be the case because workers obtain the suffrage and vote in a party to represent them, or because a party proclaiming itself to represent the working class takes power by non-democratic means, is another question. A terminological point is in order. Some advocates of socialism define it as a system in which everyone reaches his full potential, racism and sexism vanish, and 5 citizens view each other as brothers. This is a mistake. To be true to the theory of historical materialism, socialism should be defined as a nexus of property relations that eliminates capitalist exploitation. Whether such a system possesses other nice characteristics in consequence is a scientific question, one that cannot be settled by definition. A special word must be said about equality. If workers are highly heterogeneous in skills, eliminating capitalist exploitation does not eliminate inequality in incomes. Nevertheless, there has been a tradition of viewing socialism as a system of quite equal incomes. This is partly due to the level of abstraction of Marx’s thinking, in which he often viewed capitalism as characterized by a mass of homogeneous workers struggling against a small elite of homogeneous capitalists. It is, however, also due to the belief that many of the inequalities in workers’ skills come from unequal opportunities fostered by capitalism, and were capitalism to be eliminated, workers would therefore become more equal in skills. I believe this view of what socialist transformation, in the sense of Marx, would accomplish is too optimistic – on which more below, when we return to the conception of socialism as equality. In the event, the world saw two major kinds of socialist experiment: one, initiated by the Bolshevik revolution, was brought to power by a communist party which ruled undemocratically, and shunned the use of markets, which, they feared, would bring with them the old capitalist mentality, where traders tried to accumulate capital, and hence to exploit others. The other was social democracy, in which parties representing workers won state power through democratic means, and attempted to tax profits for the purpose of investment and augmenting workers’ consumption (the so-called social wage). The social democratic path did not as a principle abolish private ownership of capital assets, although some firms were nationalized. In principle, both of these techniques could abolish the kind of exploitation associated with capitalism. If communist parties were perfect agents of their collective principal, the working masses, they could set the rate of accumulation at that rate desired by workers (there is a problem here of how to aggregate workers’ disparate preferences over that rate), and then invest the surplus in that way which would best meet the interests of workers (another preference aggregation problem). And under social 6 democracy, private capital could be taxed at a rate sufficiently high that, although rates of exploitation would not be zero, they would be small. To keep capital from fleeing to more profitable venues, under that situation, workers would have to be sufficiently skilled so that, even under such a regime, capitalists’ profits would be sufficiently high. Thus, guaranteeing highly skilled labor would appear to be a part of the social-democratic formula if capital is freely mobile. With regard to equalizing the distribution of income, both the Soviet-type economies (the USSR and eastern Europe) and the Nordic social democracies did an excellent job. (Indeed, at least in the Soviet Union, it is arguable that skilled workers contributed more labor, in efficiency units, then they received back in goods.) The major difference was that the Soviet economies equalized incomes at low levels, while the social democracies did so at high levels. To what was due the failure of the Soviet economies? We still do not have a completely satisfying explanation, but it seems as if their abrogation of markets was an important factor. Although the Soviet-type economies used markets from time to time , beginning with Lenin’s introduction of the NEP in the 1920s, they were never allowed to operate with the kind of freedom that would have fostered technological innovation, and by the 1960s, it was the lack of innovation that was largely responsible for the low level of living standards. (Of course, when the state acted to concentrate talent in one sector, such as the space industry, it was able to achieve impressive results, but the Soviet economy never succeeded in fostering innovation across the board.) These problems were seen much earlier, however, in the debate around market socialism that began in the 1930s, with Oskar Lange’s argument that markets could in large part replace central planning in a socialist economy. Lange proposed that central planners announce to industrial managers prices for their inputs and outputs, and require the managers to report back with the amounts of inputs they would demand, and outputs they would produce at those prices, if they were to equate the prices to marginal costs (a necessary condition for Pareto efficiency). The planners would then sum up, observe the discrepancies in the supply and demand of each commodity, announce a second set of prices, raising those for goods in excess demand and lowering those for goods in excess supply, and go through the exercise again, hoping to eliminate the imbalances. Lange believed this process 7 would converge rapidly to an equilibrium; then the planners would post the equilibrium prices and instruct firms to produce accordingly. Lange also suggested that each household receive a certain fraction of the firms’ profits, perhaps allocated according to family size. Lange did not deal properly with the demands of consumers. But assuming that these could be incorporated into the scheme, what is the point of his kind of planning? Why not simply let the market run autonomously? Lange has no convincing answer: he did say that the central planning bureau (CPB) would be able to achieve equilibrium much faster than the market, avoiding the disequilibrium phase that he considered to be socially costly. (Today, this seems to be a quaint view, given the millions of commodities that are produced in a complex economy. Indeed, economic theory still has no full explanation of how the market ‘finds’ the equilibrium, and there are theorems that the kind of ‘t226;tonnement’ Lange proposed would, with high probability, not converge.) Perhaps Lange thought that the CPB would control economic activity through setting interest rates of various kinds, thus directing firms to invest in the directions the planners desired. Friedrich Hayek, however, offered a critique of another type. He wrote that it was an illusion to believe that managers could respond with their input demands, facing prices announced by planners, because they did not know their production functions, and therefore could not compute marginal costs. Capitalist firm managers, he said, learn how much they can produce with given inputs by the discipline of competition. It is the competitive brawl that teaches managers how to cut costs and produce efficiently, and to suppose that managers would know how to do so in the sterilized situation envisaged by Lange was wrong. Indeed, how would the CPB deal with innovation, with new commodities? The secret of real markets, Hayek argued, was that they provide incentives and a mechanism for people (entrepreneurs) with local information about needs and production possibilities to realize their ideas. Thus fixing the set of managers ex ante was already dooming the system to conservatism and inefficiency. It is interesting to note that Hayek never said that socialist managers would be opportunistic or self-serving – that they would lie to the CPB in order to influence their allotment of inputs. Hayek postulated that managers were ‘loyal and capable.’ This is in 8 sharp contrast to the critique of socialist management that emerged after 1970 among western capitalist economists, when the principal-agent problem was formulated, and ‘shirking’ and opportunism became central issues. Indeed, this raises a critical question about the failure of centrally-planned socialism: was it due to lack of incentives or to lack of coordination? Markets perform two functions: they provide incentives for workers and entrepreneurs to improve their skills and discover new commodities so as to increase their income, but they also coordinate economic activity. It may not be simple theoretically to distinguish precisely these two functions, but they are clearly different. Matching of workers to firms, for example, occurs in large part by observing wage offers; firms shop for inputs by observing price offers. Of course the system does not work perfectly, but there is doubtless a strong element of coordination engendered by a competitive price system. (Price systems do not coordinate some things properly, such as control of externalities and the supplies of public goods, and therein lies a major liberal justification of state intervention.) The history of the Soviet economy is replete with stories of poor incentives and poor coordination: we do not have a complete account of the relative importance of these two failures in the lackluster performance of centrally planned economies in their late period. One also reads, however, of how hard Soviet workers worked, and how ingenious they were at making do with poor inputs (see, for instance, Michael Burawoy). I believe it is important to answer the question posed above, for upon it may rest the possibility of a future for socialism. Suppose markets are needed mainly to generate incentives to work hard, to form skills, to invent, and so on. This implies that it will be difficult to use markets and to redistribute income in a relatively equal manner, through taxation. After all, if workers form skills in order to increase their incomes, but then their incomes are taxed away, why form skills? On the other hand, suppose that markets are needed mainly to coordinate economic activity: then in principle wage income (which would adjust competitively to reflect marginal value products) could be taxed to produce an income distribution of equality without harming production. In the second case, workers would form skills and innovate because they enjoyed doing so, or felt valued for their social contributions. 9 I suspect the coordination problem is relatively more important in the failure of centrally planned economies, and the incentive problem relatively less important, than most currently believe. Many economists, especially, assume that the opportunist kind of behavior so prevalent in the theory of homo oeconomicus is a deep aspect of human nature, and therefore that it must have been rampant in the Soviet Union. Markets are essential in any complex economy, at least for coordination, and perhaps for incentives. But, as we have seen in the Nordic countries, tremendous accomplishments with respect to income distribution can be achieved with taxation and ‘wage solidarity.’ One might say that the future of socialism lies in emulating the Nordic social democracies. They may, however, not be easy to emulate, as the solidarity of their citizenries may be due to their homogeneity – linguistic, religious, and ethnic. Perhaps welfare states of that magnitude cannot be achieved in highly heterogeneous societies. A future for socialism may still, then, require an alternative to conventional private ownership of firms with significant redistribution through taxation, because the solidarity necessary for democratic approval of that degree of redistribution may not evolve in large heterogeneous societies. If firms are not to be privately owned, as they are in the Nordic model, then a central question concerns the way that accountability of firm management is achieved. There is a principal-agent problem between the firm manager (agent) and the shareholder-citizens (principal). How do the latter keep the manager from running off with the profits and even the assets of the firm? The classical solution is that firm ownership must be highly concentrated, so that there is a small number of share holders who stand to gain huge amounts by carefully monitoring the management. In this view, distributing shares of firms equally to all citizens would destroy management accountability, resulting in unbridled corruption and inefficiency. Recently a second theory has been proposed: that the guarantor of firm accountability is the corporate raider. When the raider sees the price of a firm’s stock fall, because the firm is not performing well (perhaps due to management corruption or lack of imagination), he will buy a majority of shares and reorganize the firm to be efficient, thus increasing its stock price, and providing him with a large capital gain. 10 Here, too, if credit markets are imperfect, we need wealthy individuals to keep firms running well. If these two mechanisms of accountability exhaust the possibilities, then market economies in which firm profits are distributed in a relatively equal manner to citizens are impossible. An apparent alternative, however, exists in Germany and Japan, where firms are monitored by boards of directors consisting largely of officers of banks that have a relationship to the firm. It is beyond my scope to describe this mechanism here: suffice to say, it provides an alternative to relying upon hugely wealthy individuals for guaranteeing firm accountability. If market socialism has a future, it may well be with this kind of arrangement: firms will be monitored by bankers from the public sector, whose reputations and careers depend upon doing a good job, or they may be monitored by other stakeholders of the firm. Another alternative (proposed by Roemer), with no present worldy examples, is a system in which firm ownership is distributed to citizens in an initially equal way, but ownership rights are circumscribed. An owner will collect dividends from the firms in her portfolio, and even trade equity shares on a stock market, but she may not liquidate her equity holdings for cash. This would be accomplished by denominating corporate shares in a special unit of account. The values of shares, in that unit, would oscillate according to supply and demand, reflecting traders’ views about the future profitability of firms, as in a standard stock market. At death, a citizen’s portfolio would escheat to the Treasury, and young adults, at the age of 21, would each receive their endowment of shares. Some inequality in the values of share holdings would emerge as a consequence of differential luck and skill in the stock market during a lifetime, but that equality would not be passed on to descendents. In other words, this scheme is a method by which the nation’s profit income could be distributed in a relatively equal manner to citizens, while the virtues of a stock market, with respect to the valuation of shares, and the disciplining of management, are retained. There are surely possibilities for undermining the intentions of such a system. If there are also individuals (such as foreigners) who are allowed to invest in these firms, then possibilities arise for citizens to capitalize their holdings, to cash out their shares. Old citizens will desire that firms in which they hold shares sell their assets and pay out 11 the entire value of the firm as dividends. Whether regulation could make the system workable is an open question. Finally, there is the possibility of state ownership of firms. We do not as yet have a definitive experiment to test whether state ownership can work, for the Soviet–type experiments also involved lack of democracy; it is logically possible that democratic accountability could keep state-owned firms running efficiently. There are, however, problems here as well: politicians, to whom state-owned firm managers ultimately report, have their own interests that do not always coincide with those of the public. The electoral mechanism is probably too crude a tool to force politicians to monitor firms in the public interest. (Indeed, state-owned firms often pay their workers too much, to garner their political support.) I conjecture that non-state ownership of firms will be significant in any future socialist experiment. We return finally to the relationship of socialism to equality. Do socialists believe that an economy which implements ‘from each according to his ability, to each according to his work,’ which by definition eliminates Marxian exploitation, is desirable? Most socialists probably desire more equality than this, at least in societies where workers are highly heterogeneous in skills. Thus, socialists have come to be, and perhaps always were, more egalitarian than the Marxian definition would imply. Popular usage suggests that socialism should be defined as a regime of income equality, a departure from the Marxian tradition. The proposals we have discussed above are all concerned with the allocation of profit income. But is the allocation of profits so important with regard to equalizing the distribution of income? In contemporary advanced economies, profits (including interest and rents) comprise at most one quarter of national income; even if this part were distributed in an egalitarian manner to all households, and remained of the same size, the distribution of income would still, in most advanced countries, be quite unequal. Should, then, the difference between socialism, popularly conceived, and capitalism lie mainly in the distribution of wage income or of the role of redistributive taxation of labor income? Rather than trying to define at what Gini coefficient a society becomes socialist, one can be satisfied with ordering regimes in the world with respect to their degree of socialism. The central instruments for socialist implementation then become, as well as 12 the redistribution of profit income, intensive investment in education, with a bias towards rectifying the disadvantages children suffer due to being raised by poorly educated parents, in order to equalize market–determined labor incomes, and redistribution of labor income through taxation. The channel of intensive investment in education of the disadvantaged is important because the provision of skills has value to persons for reasons other than the instrumental one of providing income: education renders life more meaningful and fruitful. But if the education conduit alone turns out to be too costly, or too ineffective, to engender the changes in income distribution which are desirable, then other methods must be used as well. The issue of feasible socialism, therefore, will hinge upon the package of reforms that are effective, and can be realized through democratic means. How politically feasible is socialism, that is, to what degree can we expect democracies to implement the reforms that move societies further along the socialist scale? Here, the most hopeful historical evidence is provided by the Nordic and northern European countries. Two problems seem to be paramount for the continuation of the socialist trajectory in these economies: those of immigration and unemployment. The welfare states of the northern European countries, as mentioned earlier, evolved during the period when their populations were largely homogeneous, along ethnic, linguistic, and religious dimensions. Homogeneity may be a necessary condition for the democratic implementation of significant redistribution, if the welfare state is motivated by either a purely redistributive or an insurance function. For, with respect to the insurance function, it is not in the interest of highly educated and high-wage natives in, let us say, Denmark, to pool their risks with poorly educated, low-wage immigrants. And with respect to the purely redistributive function, ethnic, linguistic, and religious heterogeneity reduce solidarity, to put it mildly, which must be the motivation of purely redistributive taxation. Unemployment is a problem not only for the deleterious welfare effects its victims suffer, but because it is a severe form of economic inefficiency. If ‘socialist’ countries have high unemployment levels, and ‘capitalist’ countries low levels, eventually the inefficiency of the former may well reduce per capita income significantly below that of the latter, and populations of the socialist countries will begin to find the 13 higher incomes offered, on average, by the capitalist regimes, an attractive alternative. If we assume that, in the coming century, the United States (and, let us say, China) continue to offer low- unemployment, low- taxation, high-growth regimes, but with relatively little redistribution, then democratic polities in Europe and the rest of the world may be reluctant to move further on the socialist spectrum. This, of course, assumes that there is some sacrifice in economic growth entailed by redistributive institutions, a point that I have not defended here, but have taken for granted, and which may be incorrect. Indeed, a growing literature asserts that equality increases productivity (see Bardhan and Bowles). It is perfectly natural for fertility rates to fall when social insurance replaces the family as the source of income in old age: and smaller families, probably more than anything, entail the liberation of women. (They are also, of course, an effect of that liberation.) But European fertility rates now necessitate either a significant flow of immigrants from poorer countries, or a sharp decline in per capita incomes in Europe for retired workers, or an increase in the length of working life (which itself would exacerbate the unemployment problem). So lower fertility renders the progress towards socialism more complex at least, if not infeasible. Consequently, the issue of multi-culturalism becomes a key intellectual problem for socialists. What degree of integration or assimilation of immigrants is necessary for democratic European polities to be willing and interested to continue and perhaps expand their welfare states? (Recall, we refer here not simply to the redistributive motive, but to the risk-bearing motive, of natives wishing to pool risks with immigrants.) We do not, I think, yet know the answer. And will this degree of assimilation, whatever it turns out to be, be acceptable to poor Southerners or Easterners who are contemplating migration to the North or West? Socialism, in the sense of equality of incomes, with a democratic implementation requires either a self-interested insurance motive or a selfless solidaristic motive among the majority of voter-citizens. We can hope that as national populations come to experience more equality, they would come to have a deeper preference for it: socialists, at least, believe that solidaristic preferences can intensify with the experience of equality, because equality is a public good, a fact that will be appreciated when it is experienced. 14 (Indeed, we have not, in this article, discussed the negative externalities that socialists believe accompany a regime with a highly concentrated ownership of private firms, in which corporate and even state policy is set to further the interests of only the wealthiest sliver of society. ) But the initial transitions along this path, taken by relatively selfcentered voters, must come from the insurance motive. Here, then, is an important problem for progress towards socialism in our time. References Bardhan, P. and S. Bowles, 2000. “Wealth inequality, wealth constraints and economic performance,” in A. Atkinson and F. Bourguignon, eds., Handbook of Income Distribution, Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Press Burawoy, M. and J. Lukacs, 1985. “Mythologies of work: A comparison of firms in state socialism and advanced capitalism,” American Sociological Review 50, 723-737 Hayek, F.A. 1940. “Socialist calculation: the competitive ‘solution’,” Economica 7, 125-149 Lange, O. 1956 [1936]. “On the economic theory of socialism,” in B. Lippincott, ed., On the economic theory of socialism, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press Luxemburg, R. 1972 [1913]. The accumulation of capital , New York: Monthly Review Press Ostroy, J. and L. Makowski, 1993. “General equilibrium and market socialism: Clarifying the logic of competitive markets,” in P. Bardhan and J. Roemer, eds., MarketsSocialism: The current debate, New York: Oxford University Press Roemer, J.E. 1994. A future for socialism, Cambrige, Mass. : Harvard University Press Roemer, J.E. and J. Silvestre, 1993. “The proportional solution for economies with both private and public ownership,” Journal of economic theory 59, 426-444 |
|